45 pages • 1 hour read
A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
Summary
Background
Chapter Summaries & Analyses
Key Figures
Themes
Index of Terms
Important Quotes
Essay Topics
Tools
In this chapter, Lewis anticipates some of the questions and hesitancies which readers might bring against his argument. In response to his suggestion that human reason is rooted in the eternal reason of God, some might wonder why, then, human minds seem impaired by mere physical circumstance: as for instance, by injury, disability, or the effects of drugs or alcohol. Lewis responds that human minds are not pure extensions of divine reason, but are inextricably physical in their operations, and thus bound by the limitations of physicality: “A man’s Rational thinking is just so much of his share in eternal Reason as the state of his brain allows to become operative” (62).
A second misgiving which Lewis identifies is that which might lead readers to wonder why, if the supernatural exists and exercises such an all-pervasive influence, it is so difficult to perceive. One might suspect that the supernatural should be as obvious to discern as nature itself, especially if it is intimately tied to our own rational operations. But Lewis points out that it is often the most all-pervasive things which escape our awareness: our use of the grammatical rules of our own mother tongue, for instance, or the operations of our faculty of sight—both of which we use all the time without conscious awareness because they are the framework through which we perceive the world. So too with the supernatural: It is indeed all around us, intimately tied to our own consciousness, but it is so obvious as to be easily overlooked. Lewis further points out that our own lack of awareness of it might be the result of our own historical-cultural moment, seeing as most other human societies throughout history appear to have been very aware of the supernatural.
Lewis moves on to consider popular but misguided arguments against miracles. Among these common misconceptions is the view that miracles cannot happen because miracles break the laws of nature, and earlier generations of people believed in miracles only because they didn’t know about natural laws. Both of these points are incorrect in Lewis’s view. Most ancient people knew the basic principles of natural causation very well. If they did not, the idea of a miracle would have been meaningless to them, since a miracle, by definition, means that something out of the ordinary is happening. Lewis argues that miracles do not “break” the laws of nature. Rather, miracles are an interruption introduced from outside the system, to which the laws of nature quite naturally adjust, responding according to their established patterns. “Those who believe in miracles are not denying that there is such a norm or rule: they are only saying that it can be suspended” (72).
A second red herring is the widespread argument that belief in miracles comes from unenlightened eras of history in which humanity believed it stood at the center of the universe (and thus, the center of God’s affections), but that scientific discoveries regarding the scope of the universe have since demonstrated human insignificance. Lewis finds this argument unpersuasive, not least because it reveals a prejudice against previous historical eras which does not hold up to the light of careful inspection. Further, it is simply not the case that Christian theology ever argued that God graced humanity with miracles because humans were important; it rather argued that God’s miracles were an example of incredible grace, because humans were so undeserving of God’s favor. The relative size of human beings when compared to the universe is no sign of importance or unimportance. If size was a mark of importance, then we would count a person more important for being taller, or less important for being shorter; the fact that we do not shows that this common perception is, as Lewis suggests, a red herring.
Lewis clarifies the terminology of “laws of nature,” suggesting there are several different possibilities for what the laws actually are: either brute facts of nature, statistical averages indicating what usually happens, or necessary truths (like those in mathematics). In any of the above views of the laws of nature, Lewis argues, miracles are possible: Miracles are not an instance of the laws being broken, but rather of something from outside the system being added in, with which natural laws quite naturally comply, and follow from that addition as their ordered procedures dictate. The three possible views of the laws of nature all express a reality which holds when all other things are equal, but in the case of miracles, all other things are not equal—something more is being interposed from the outside—and so while no laws are broken by miracles, they must adjust themselves to the new reality which the miracle has created. The laws of nature are not themselves the active agents which make anything happen; they simply govern the motions of those things which are already happening, and so if something new is added from outside the system, the laws of nature will simply take over the operations of the new addition from the point that it was interposed. “[A miracle’s] cause is the activity of God: its results follow according to Natural Law” (95). In this way, rather than representing an aberration in natural systems, miracles actually highlight the harmonious balance of natural processes, which can take even divine interpositions and weave them into the orderly dance of matter and energy.
In this chapter, Lewis addresses a concern which was a major stumbling block in his own journey of considering supernaturalism, but which he admits might not be a consideration for others. Nevertheless, he includes it here, in part to point out the error of assuming that nature itself is the absolute reality, rather than merely a contingent being. One of the things that made supernaturalism distasteful to him in the past was the Christian idea that nature was ordered and arranged by an intelligence, rather than existing entirely on its own. To Lewis, the disappointment engendered by this idea was like the letdown of seeing a remarkable piece of natural beauty but then learning that it was actually a landscape that had been tinkered with behind the scenes to evoke a particular reaction; the difference between seeing a spontaneous event and watching a puppet show. Nature seemed to lose something of its wildness.
Later, however, Lewis discerned that the supernaturalist view of nature not only preserved a sense of nature’s wildness but even expanded upon it. To the Christian, nature’s beauty certainly does reflect the order and majesty of its divine designer, but nature, as a creature of God, is also endowed with its own sort of personality, just as any other creature would be. Like any particular thing (rather than a vague generalized reality, as many naturalists conceive of nature), nature in the Christian view has its own character, much as the different languages of the world all come with their own particular flair and temperament. “Everything becomes different when we recognize that Nature is a creature, a created thing, with its own particular tang and flavor” (102). Lewis now found nature not only wild, but knowable in a rather personal way, one that had not been open to him when he was a naturalist.
This second set of chapters represents a transition in the structure of the book. Heretofore, Lewis has been discussing the philosophical foundations of naturalism and supernaturalism, using that philosophical mode of discourse to pursue his polemic against naturalism. In these chapters, however, he shifts toward answering objections and offering an analysis of popular conceptions regarding miracles. While Lewis continues to use philosophical explanations, in these chapters it is the popular ideas which set the agenda for discussion, not the philosophical categories involved.
Part of Lewis’s broad appeal as a writer is that his academic background is balanced out by his plain-spoken style and his facility in understanding and dealing with readers’ issues of concern. He was well-known for cultivating a writing style that was significantly more conversational than was typical of Oxford dons, for example using vivid analogies that were often based on widely accessible features of human experience. In Chapter 6, for example, he draws upon daily experiences of speech and sight in such a way as to make an analogy for the all-pervasiveness of God’s presence. He aims for a personal voice, as if it comes from a conversation with a friend. A prime example of this is the way he reveals his own previous difficulties with the idea of miracles (Chapter 9), building his credibility (or ethos, in rhetorical terms) by establishing that he once shared the reader’s likely skepticism.
The same themes appear in these chapters as in the opening sections of the book, though both are more prominent here, as the book develops its argument. The theme of Cultural Bias as the Root of the Modern Rejection of Miracles comes into clear focus in these chapters, as Lewis one by one rebuts the various popular arguments which people bring against the idea of miracles. In some cases, Lewis specifically points out issues of bias undergirding these popular misconceptions, as when he demonstrates the unwarranted historical prejudice with which many modern people regard the pre-modern world. To view people from earlier periods as superstitious and ignorant of the laws of nature is, as Lewis shows, little more than an expression of cultural bias. This is a core component of Lewis’s argument from reason—his use of logic, or logos, to disarm modern objections to the existence of miracles. In this case, he points out an irony: Modern skeptics view the belief in miracles as evidence that pre-modern people were ignorant of natural laws, but in fact, knowledge of natural laws is a prerequisite for the recognition of miracles, as one cannot recognize that which stands outside the ordinary patterns of nature without first being aware of such patterns.
Having shown that debunked modern cultural biases against pre-modern beliefs, Lewis again uses logos to argue that Miracles Do Not Break the Laws of Nature. Lewis points out that this fundamental objection to the existence of miracles relies on the presupposition that nature is all there is—that is, it begs the question, starting from an unproven premise. If nature is all that exists, then nature’s laws apply everywhere, and miracles are impossible. However, Lewis questions the underlying premise, suggesting that nature exists within a frame and that something else can—or must—exist outside that frame. Since miracles originate from outside the frame of nature, they do not violate natural laws but instead suspend or supersede them.
The laws of nature, for their part, have no agency of their own, but are simply the norms and rules by which events proceed once the causes have been established. Since miracles have their own causes from beyond the system, the laws of nature automatically adjust and ensure that the effects of those events follow as dictated by the natural system. This theme ties together with the former one as well: since one of the main objections that Lewis’s contemporaries had against the idea of miracles was the sensibility that they contravened natural law, Lewis’s dismantling of that argument helps to show that the philosophical stance against miracles is actually more a matter of the prevailing cultural bias than of logical or scientific arguments.
Unlock all 45 pages of this Study Guide
Plus, gain access to 9,150+ more expert-written Study Guides.
Including features:
By C. S. Lewis